Prefer Accept Reject voting: Difference between revisions

imported>Homunq
No edit summary
 
(24 intermediate revisions by one other user not shown)
Line 1:
Prefer Accept Reject (PAR) voting works as follows:
 
# '''Voters Prefer, Accept, or Reject each candidate.''' On ballots which don't explicitly use "Reject", or for candidates with less than 25% "Prefer", blanks count as "Reject"; otherwise, blanks count as "Accept".
# '''Tally 1 point for each "Prefer"''' for each candidate.
# '''Of the candidates that are both "viable"''' (at least 25% Prefer) '''and "acceptable"''' (no more than 50% reject), the one with most "Prefer"s is called the leader.
# EachOut "prefer"of isthe worthcandidates 1(if point.any) Forwith viableno candidates,more eachthan 50% "acceptReject", onfind the one with the most points. '''For aevery ballot which doesn't prefer"Prefer" thethis leader isfrontrunner, also worthadd 1 point. '''Mostfor pointseach wins"Accept".'''
# If the frontrunner still has the most points, they win. Otherwise, the winner is the candidate with fewest "Reject" ratings.
 
To express it in a single sentence: if the most-preferred non-majority-rejected candidate, X, has more non-reject votes than any other candidate has non-reject votes that aren't below X, then X wins; otherwise, the least-rejected candidate wins.
Note that the procedure above will always elect a viable candidate if any exist. It will usually, but not always, elect the "leader" as defined above. Each candidate's score at the end can be seen as an approval total.
 
Note that the procedure above will always elect a candidate with no more than 50% "Reject", if any exist. This is because, if any exist, one of them will be the frontrunner, and they will thus score points equal to at least 50% of the voters.
 
Each candidate's score at the end can be seen as an approval total, and is thus suitable for combining with approval totals from other jurisdictions in a system like the National Popular Vote Interstate Compact.
 
A related system which passes [[FBC]] is [[FBPPAR]]. This has the same steps, except that voters can choose to mark any of their "preferred" candidates as "stand aside". "Stand aside" preferences are counted as rejections when finding the leader, but as preference when assigning points.
Line 15 ⟶ 20:
== Criteria compliance ==
 
PAR voting passes the [[majority criterion]], the [[mutual majority criterion]], the [[majority loser criterion]], [[Local independence of irrelevant alternatives]] (under the assumption of fixed "honest" ratings for each voter for each candidate), [[Independence of clone alternatives]], [[Monotonicity]], [[polytime]], [[resolvability]], and O(N²) [[summability]]. (It is also possible to run it in no more than 3 counting rounds, each of which is O(N) summable.)
 
There are a few criteria for which it does not pass as such, but where it passes related but weaker criteria. These include:
Line 21 ⟶ 26:
* It fails [[Independence of irrelevant alternatives]], but passes [[Local independence of irrelevant alternatives]].
 
* It fails the [[Condorcet criterion]], but forif anythere setis ofa voters such that an honestvoted majority Condorcet winner existsX, therethen alwaysany existsfaction a(defined strongas equilibriumthe set of strictlyvoters semi-honestwho ballotsprefer thatX>Y,Z, electsor thatalternately CW.as (Notethe thatset thiswho isprefer not trueY>X>Z, for anysome strictlyY and Z) can ensure that X beats Z, using semi-rankedhonest Condorcetballots system!(X>>Z or YX>>Z, respectively).
 
* It fails the [[participation criterion]] but passes the [[semi-honest participation criterion]].
 
* It fails O(N)the [[summabilitylater-no-help criterion]], but canpasses getif thatthere summabilityis withat two-passleast tallyingone (firstcandidate determinerejected who's disqualified,by thenunder retally)50%.
 
* It may passfails the majority[[consistency criterion]], the [[Condorcet loser criterion]], (?)[[reversibility]], the [[Strategy-free criterion]], and the [[later-no-harm criterion]].
 
* It fails the [[later-no-help criterion]], but passes if there is at least one candidate above the qualification thresholds (which is always true, for instance, if there are some three candidates who get 3 different ratings on every ballot).
 
It fails the [[consistency criterion]], the [[Condorcet loser criterion]], [[reversibility]], the [[Strategy-free criterion]], and the [[later-no-harm criterion|later-no-harm]] criterion.
 
=== Favorite betrayal? ===
Line 44 ⟶ 45:
* 40: C>B
 
None are disqualifiedmajority-rejected, and C is the leaderfrontrunner. Points are: A, 60; B, 55; C, 55; X, 35. CA wins. However, if 611 of the last group of voters strategically betrayed their true favorite C, the situation would be as follows:
 
* 30: AX>B (That is, on 35 ballots, A and X are preferred, B is accepted, and C is rejected)
Line 50 ⟶ 51:
* 15: B>A
* 10: B>AC
* 3429: C>B
* 611: B
 
Now, C is not viable with 51% rejection; so B is the leader. Since C is no longer the leader, B gets the 34 points from C voters, and wins. The strategy succeeded; the strategic voters are better off.
 
However, there are several ways to "rescue" FBC-like behavior for this system.
Line 59 ⟶ 60:
For one, we could add a "stand aside" option to the ballot, as described in [[FBPPAR]].
 
For another, the B>AC voters could simply reject C, the strongest rival of their favorite, and B would win with no need for favorite betrayal.
 
And finally, note that in any scenario where it fails that for some small group, there is a rational strategy for some superset of that group which does not involve betrayal. For instance, in first scenario above, if 16 of the C>B voters switch to CB, then B is the leader and wins without them having to rate C below their true feelings.
Line 67 ⟶ 68:
{{Tenn_voting_example}}
 
Assume voters in each city preferred their own city; rejected any city that is over 200 miles away or is the farthest city; andexplicitly accepted the closest other city; and left the rest blank. In the following table, the quantities in parentheses are explicit votes, while the implicit totals (including blank votes) are unparenthesized.
 
<div class="floatright">
Line 73 ⟶ 74:
!City
!P
!(A)
!A
!(R)
!R
!tally
Line 79 ⟶ 82:
!bgcolor="#fff"|Memphis
|bgcolor="#fff"|42
|bgcolor="#fff"|(0)
|bgcolor="#fff"|0
|bgcolor="#fcc"|(58)
|bgcolor="#fcc"|58
|bgcolor="#fcc"|42
Line 85 ⟶ 90:
!bgcolor="#fff"|Nashville
|bgcolor="#fff"|26
|bgcolor="#fff"|(42)
|bgcolor="#fff"|74
|bgcolor="#fff"|(0)
|bgcolor="#fff"|0
|bgcolor="#cfc"|100
Line 91 ⟶ 98:
!bgcolor="#fff"|Chattanooga
|bgcolor="#fcc"|15
|bgcolor="#fff"|(43)
|bgcolor="#fff"|43
|bgcolor="#fff"|(0)
|bgcolor="#fff"|42
|bgcolor="#fccfff"|1558
|-
!bgcolor="#fff"|Knoxville
|bgcolor="#fcc"|17
|bgcolor="#fff"|41(15)
|bgcolor="#fff"|4215
|bgcolor="#fccfff"|17(0)
|bgcolor="#fcc"|68
|bgcolor="#fcc"|32
|}
</div>
 
Memphis is rejected by a majority, and is nonviable. Chattanooga and Knoxville both get less than 25% preference, so they are also nonviable. Nashville is the leader, and wins with a tally of 100%. This is a strong equilibrium; no rational strategy from any faction or combination thereof would change the winner. Knoxville and/or Chattanooga could each prevent the other from being disqualified and even get the other to temporarily be the frontrunner, but Nashville would still win with a tally of at least 68 (the ballots of Nashville and Memphis).
 
(If Memphis voters rejected Nashville, then Chattanooga or Knoxville could win by conspiring to reject Nashville and accept Memphis. However, Nashville could stop this by rejecting them. Thus this strategy would not work without extreme foolishness from both Memphis and Nashville voters, ''and'' extreme amounts of strategy from the others.)
Line 111 ⟶ 122:
=== Logic for 25%-preferred threshold (step 2) ===
 
The 25%-preferred threshold in step 21 is not purely arbitrary; it is exactly enough so that, in a 3-candidate election where all voters give all three grades, there will always be at least 1 candidate who passes the thresholds to not be disqualified. In other words: if a minority supports a rejected candidate, while a majority divides preferences between two candidates while accepting the other, then at least one of those two will not be disqualified. This does not hold for an election with 4 or more candidates, because the majority could split its preferences more than two ways; but even in those cases, it is usually reasonable to hope that the top 3 candidates combined will get enough preferences to ensure that at least one of them is above the 25% threshold.
 
[[Category:Graded Bucklin systemsmethods]]