Condorcet winner criterion: Difference between revisions

m (Handle possible ambiguity wrt majority criterion (or majority criterion being too lax).)
 
(33 intermediate revisions by 5 users not shown)
Line 1:
{{Wikipedia}}<!-- {{cleanup|date=February 2020}} -->
[[File:Finding the Condorcet winner.png|thumb|623x623px|Finding the Condorcet winner using [[Pairwise counting|pairwise counting]].]]<!-- {{cleanup|date=February 2020}} -->
 
An [[electoral system]] satisfies the "'''Condorcet winner criterion"''', also known as the '''Condorcet criterion''', if it always chooses the Condorcet winner when one exists. The "Condorcet winner" is sometimes referred to as the "'''Condorcet candidate"''', "'''Pairwisepairwise Championchampion'''" (PC),or '''"beats-all winner''',". orThe "'''Condorcet winner"''' (CW) of an [[election]] is the candidate who is preferred by more voters than any other candidate in [[Pairwise counting|pairwise matchups]]. This is determined by observing whether more voters rank or score the Condorcet winner higher than each of the other candidates than the other way around.
 
The '''Condorcet winner criterion''' for a [[voting system]] is that it chooses the beats-all winner when one exists. Any method conforming to the Condorcet criterion is known as a [[Condorcet method]]. Though Condorcet winner criterion is sometimes referred to as simply the "Condorcet criterion", it's important not to confuse the Condorcet winner criterion with the "[[Condorcet loser criterion]]" .
 
Mainly because of [[Condorcet paradox|Condorcet's voting paradox]], a beats-all winner will not always exist in a given set of votes. However, there will always be a smallest group of candidates such that more voters prefer anyone in the group over anyone outside of the group. If the beats-all winner exists, they will be the only candidate in this group, which is called the [[Smith set]]. Voting methods that always elect from the Smith set are known as "[[Smith-efficient]]".  
As an example, if there are 3 candidates, with head-to-head matchups indicating a 51% majority prefers the second candidate over the first, and a 43% plurality prefer the second over 37% preferring the third (with 20% of voters having no preference), then the second candidate gets more votes than their competitors in all matchups and so they are the Condorcet winner.
 
==Example==
Mainly because of [[Condorcet paradox|Condorcet's voting paradox]], a beats-all winner will not always exist in a given set of votes. However, there will always be a smallest group of candidates such that more voters prefer anyone in the group over anyone outside of the group. If the beats-all winner exists, they will be the only candidate in this group, which is called the [[Smith set]]. Voting methods that always elect from the Smith set are known as "[[Smith-efficient]]".
As an example, if there are 3 candidates, with head-to-head matchups indicating a 51% majority prefers the second candidate over the first, and a 43% plurality prefer the second over 37% preferring the third (with 20% of voters having no preference), then the second candidate gets more votes than their competitors in all matchups and so they are the Condorcet winner.
 
===Detailed example===
== A more general wording of Condorcet criterion definition ==
Suppose the voters had been polled on their preferences among the candidates, and the following preferences in head-to-head matchups are produced between French Fries (FF), Hamburger (H), and Cookies (C) (FF>C shows the number of voters who prefer FF over C, for example):
 
FF>H:51, FF>C:60
'''Requirements:'''
 
H>FF:49, H>C:70
# The voting system must allow the voter to vote as many transitive pairwise preferences as desired. (Typically that's in the form of an unlimited ranking)
 
# If there are one or more unbeaten candidates, then the winner should be an unbeaten candidate. (Though usually this requirement is simply "If there is one candidate who beats all others, then they must win.")
C>FF:40, C>H:20
 
If for each pair of candidates, we subtract the number of votes preferring the second candidate over the first from the number of votes preferring the first to the second, then we'll know which one won the head-to-head matchup.
 
(Margins)
<p style="border: 5px dotted green;">FF>H:2 (Win), FF>C:20 (Win)</p>
 
H>FF:-2, H>C:20 (Win)
 
C>FF:-20, C>H:-50
 
The Condorcet winner (if one exists) will be the candidate who got a majority of votes (as indicated by the positive margin) in all of their head-to-head matchups.
 
FF (French Fries) is the CW here.
 
==A more general wording of Condorcet criterion definition==
 
'''Requirements:'''
 
#The voting system must allow the voter to vote as many transitive pairwise preferences as desired. (Typically that's in the form of an unlimited ranking)
#If there are one or more unbeaten candidates, then the winner should be an unbeaten candidate. (Though usually this requirement is simply "If there is one candidate who beats all others, then they must win."; see the below section on Weak Condorcet winners for a critique of this definition)
 
'''Traditional definition of "beat":'''
Line 23 ⟶ 45:
}}
 
== Majority Condorcet criterion ==
 
The majority Condorcet criterion is the same as the above, but with "beat" replaced by "majority-beat", defined to be "X majority-beats Y iff over 50% voters vote X over Y." Thus, a '''majority Condorcet winner''' is a Condorcet winner who majority-beats all other candidates.
Line 32 ⟶ 54:
 
[[Approval voting]], [[Range voting]], [[Borda count]], [[plurality voting]], and [[instant-runoff voting]] do not comply with the Condorcet Criterion. However, any voting method that collects enough information to detect pairwise preferences (i.e. scoring or ranking methods) can be "forced" to comply with the Condorcet criterion by automatically electing the Condorcet winner if one exists (or alternatively, eliminating all candidates not in the Smith Set) before doing anything else.
 
== Occurrences in real elections ==
 
Most real elections have a Condorcet winner. Andrew Myers, who operates the [[online poll|Condorcet Internet Voting Service]], found that 83% of the nonpolitical CIVS elections with at least 10 votes had a Condorcet winner, with the figure rising to 98.8% for elections with at least 300 votes.<ref name="CIVS">{{cite conference |url=https://www.cs.cornell.edu/andru/papers/civs24/ |title=The Frequency of Condorcet Winners in Real Non-Political Elections |last=Myers |first=A. C. |author-link=https://www.cs.cornell.edu/andru/ |date=March 2024 |conference=61st Public Choice Society Conference}}</ref>
 
A database of 189 ranked United States election from 2004 to 2022 contained only one Condorcet cycle: the [[2021 Minneapolis Ward 2 city council election]].<ref name="GSM2023">{{cite arXiv | last=Graham-Squire | first=Adam | last2=McCune | first2=David | title=An Examination of Ranked Choice Voting in the United States, 2004-2022 |eprint=2301.12075v2 | date=2023-01-28 | class=econ.GN}}</ref> While this indicates a very high rate of Condorcet winners, it's possible that some of the effect is due to general [[two-party domination]].
 
==Commentary==
On a one-dimensional [[political spectrum]], the beats-all winner will be at the position of the median voter.
 
===Compromise candidate===
The Condorcet winner/[[Smith set]] is a common [[equilibrium]] point in many voting methods. This is because a majority/plurality of voters have no incentive to deviate towards another candidate.
 
On a one-dimensional [[political spectrum]], the beats-all winner will be at the position of the median voter. See the following example:
 
[[File:Left,_Center,_Right.png]]
 
Supposing this is the voter distribution, with three candidates '''L'''eft, '''C'''enter, and '''R'''ight, with voters concentrated in each area of the distribution as given, with the yellow voters preferring Left, the green preferring Center, and the blue preferring Right. Then the Condorcet winner is Center, because a majority - the Center voters plus the Left voters - prefers Center to Right, and another majority prefers Center to Left.
 
[[Instant-runoff voting]], which does not pass the Condorcet criterion, fails to detect Center's support and thus Center is eliminated early. However, if the majority preferring Center to the IRV winner knew this in advance, they could have used [[compromising]] strategy to force Center to be elected anyway. See below.
 
Note that the "Center" candidate is only the center of the voters' distribution. If this were a conservative party primary, the center of the distribution would likely be a conservative candidate, not a centrist.
 
===Equilibrium point for various voting methods===
The [[Bipartisan set]] (a subset of the [[Smith set]]) is the common [[equilibrium]] point of most voting methods. This is because a majority/plurality of voters have no incentive to deviate towards another candidate. The Condorcet criterion can thus be considered a type of [[Declared strategy voting|automatic strategy]], which reduces the need for [[compromising]] strategy by electing candidates who could have won with majority-strength compromising.
 
An example for [[Approval voting]]:
 
35: A>B|>C
 
34: B>C|
 
31: C>B|>A
 
B is the CW. If voters approve everyone they ranked before the "|", then B is approved by all voters, and wins. If any of the three groups of voters here raises their approval threshold (only approves their 1st choice), then another group has an incentive to maintain their approval threshold where it is i.e. if C-top voters stop approving B, then the 69 voters who prefer B>C have an incentive to move their approval thresholds between B and C to ensure B is approved by a majority and C is not. Note that this requires both accurate polling and coordinated [[Strategic voting|strategic voting]].
 
===Non-complying methods===
Non-ranking methods such as [[plurality voting|plurality]] and [[approval voting|approval]] cannot comply with the Condorcet criterion because they do not allow each voter to fully specify their preferences. But instant-runoff voting allows each voter to rank the candidates, yet it still does not comply. A simple example will prove that IRV fails to comply with the Condorcet criterion.
 
Line 43 ⟶ 94:
 
<blockquote><table>
<tr><td align="right">499:</td><td align="left">A&gt;B&gt;C</td></tr>
<tr><td align="right">498:</td><td align="left">C&gt;B&gt;A</td></tr>
<tr><td align="right">3:</td><td align="left">B&gt;C&gt;A</td></tr>
</table></blockquote>
 
In this case, B is preferred to A by 501 votes to 499, and B is
preferred to C by 502 to 498, hence B is preferred to both A and C. So according to the Condorcet criteria, B should win. By contrast, according to the rules of IRV, B is ranked first by the fewest voters and is eliminated, and C wins with the transferred voted from B; in plurality voting A wins with the most first choices. Note that B and C are a [[Mutual majority criterion|mutual majority]], so most majority rule-based methods would rule A out of winning. If A drops out, then B becomes the majority's 1st choice; so this is an example of IRV failing [[Independence of irrelevant alternatives|independence of irrelevant alternatives]].
preferred to C by 502 to 498, hence B is preferred to both A and C. So
according to the Condorcet criteria, B should win. By contrast, according to the rules of IRV, B is ranked first by the fewest voters and is eliminated, and C wins with the transferred voted from B; in plurality voting A wins with the most first choices.
 
RangeSee [[Score voting#Majority-related does not comply because it allows for the difference between 'rankings'criteria]] to matter. E.g. 51 people might rate A at 100, and B at 90, while 49 people rate A at 0, and B at 100. Condorcet would consider this 51 people voting A>B, and 49 voting B>A, and A would win. Range voting would see thishow asScore Acan having support of 5100/100 = 51%, and B support of (51*90+49*100)/100 = 94.9%; range voting advocates would probably say that in this casefail the Condorcet winner is not the socially ideal winnercriterion. In general however, it is expected that the Condorcet winner (and Smith Set candidates in general) will almost alwaysusually be very high-utility, wheneven comparedif tothey are not the highest-utility candidate (the utilitarian winner).
 
===Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives===
Note that the Condorcet criterion also implies the following criterion which is somewhat related to Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives: removing losing candidates can't change the result of an election if there is a Condorcet winner.<ref name="Schulze 2018 with footnote">{{cite arXiv | last=Schulze | first=Markus | title=The Schulze Method of Voting | date=2018-03-15 | eprint=1804.02973 |page=351|class=cs.GT}} "The Condorcet criterion for single-winner elections (section 4.7) is important because, when there is a Condorcet winner b ∈ A, then it is still a Condorcet winner when alternatives a1,...,an ∈ A \ {b} are removed. So an alternative b ∈ A doesn’t owe his property of being a Condorcet winner to the presence of some other alternatives. Therefore, when we declare a Condorcet winner b ∈ A elected whenever a Condorcet winner exists, we know that no other alternatives a1,...,an ∈ A \ {b} have changed the result of the election without being elected."</ref> In addition, adding candidates who are pairwise beaten by the Condorcet winner (when one exists) can't change the result of the election.
 
===Weak Condorcet winners===
 
Sometimes there is no Condorcet winner, but there may be candidate(s) who are preferred by at least as many voters as all other candidates (i.e. they beat '''or''' tie all other candidates; as many voters rank or score them higher or equally as each of the other candidates as the other way around), who are known as weak Condorcet winners. While it may thus seem reasonable that a Condorcet method should pass a condition of always electing solely from the set of weak Condorcet winners when no regular Condorcet winner exists and at least one weak Condorcet winner exists, this guaranteeably leads to failures of reversal symmetry and clone immunity, and so it may be better to say that the set of weak Condorcet winners should have some, but not total priority to win. Example (parentheses are used to indicate implied rankings):<blockquote>3 A(>B1=B2=B3)
Line 70 ⟶ 125:
 
 
3 B1(>A)</blockquote>Now both of A and B1 are weak CWs, because they both pairwise tie each other. In this particular example, since there is nothing that distinguishes either candidate from the other, the neutrality criterion requires that both A and B1 must have an equal probability of winning i.e. both must have a 50% chance. This means that removing clones of B1 increased B1's chances of winning (which were originally at 0%, since A was guaranteed to win earlier i.e. had a 100% chance of winning.) <ref name="Schulze 2018 p206">https://arxiv.org/abs/{{cite arXiv | last=Schulze | first=Markus | title=The Schulze Method of Voting | date=2018-03-15 | eprint=1804.02973v602973 p|page=206–207|class=cs. 206-207GT}}</ref>
 
Weak CWs have also been called Condorcet non-losers, with the requirement that they always win when they exist being called Exclusive-Condorcet. <ref>{{Cite web|url=http://www.votingmatters.org.uk/ISSUE3/P5.HTM#r2|title=Voting matters, Issue 3: pp 8-15|last=|first=|date=|website=www.votingmatters.org.uk|url-status=live|archive-url=|archive-date=|access-date=2020-05-09|quote=Exclusive-Condorcet (see Fishburn[2]). If there is a Condorcet non-loser, then at least one Condorcet non-loser should be elected.}}</ref>
Note that the Condorcet criterion also implies the following criterion which is somewhat related to Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives: removing losing candidates can't change the result of an election if there is a Condorcet winner. <ref>https://arxiv.org/abs/1804.02973 The Schulze Method of Voting p.351 "The Condorcet criterion for single-winner elections (section 4.7) is important because, when there is a Condorcet winner b ∈ A, then it is still a Condorcet winner when alternatives a1,...,an ∈ A \ {b} are removed. So an alternative b ∈ A doesn’t owe his property of being a Condorcet winner to the presence of some other alternatives. Therefore, when we declare a Condorcet winner b ∈ A elected whenever a Condorcet winner exists, we know that no other alternatives a1,...,an ∈ A \ {b} have changed the result of the election without being elected."</ref> In addition, adding candidates who are pairwise beaten by the Condorcet winner (when one exists) can't change the result of the election.
 
== Multi-winner generalizations ==
Schulze has proposed a generalization of the Condorcet criterion for multi-winner methods:<ref name="Schulze 2018">{{cite webarXiv | last=Schulze | first=Markus | title=The Schulze Method of Voting | website=arXiv.org | date=2018-03-15 | urleprint=https://arxiv.org/abs/1804.02973v602973 | access-datepage=2020-02-11351|pageclass=351cs.GT}}</ref> Suppose all but M+1 candidates are eliminated from the ballots, and the remaining candidates include candidate ''b''. If ''b'' is always a winner when electing M winners from the M+1 remaining candidates, no matter who the other M remaining candidates are, then ''b'' is an M-seat Condorcet winner.
 
A method passes the M-seat Condorcet criterion if its M-seat election outcome always contains such a ''b'' when he exists, and passes the multi-winner Condorcet criterion if it passes the M-seat Condorcet criterion for all M.
Line 83 ⟶ 138:
Note that Bloc Ranked Pairs and Bloc Score voting (if scored methods are considered) would pass this criterion, though they are not proportional, and the latter is not a Condorcet method in the single-winner case. So it may make more sense to consider Schulze's criterion as one of several that a multi-winner method ought to pass to be considered a Condorcet multi-winner or Condorcet PR method, rather than the definitive one.
 
In addition to Schulze's generalization, Gehrein, and Aziz ''et al.'' have proposed different multi-winner generalizations, based on the concept of stability.<ref name="Aziz">{{cite arXiv | last1=Aziz | first1=Haris | last2=Elkind | first2=Edith | last3=Faliszewski | first3=Piotr | last4=Lackner | first4=Martin | last5=Skowron | first5=Piotr | title=The Condorcet Principle for Multiwinner Elections: From Shortlisting to Proportionality | date=2017-01-27 | eprint=1701.08023 | class=cs.GT}}</ref>
== Abstract Condorcet Criterion ==
 
==Abstract Condorcet Criterion==
See [[Self-referential Smith-efficient Condorcet method]].
 
The Condorcet criterion can be abstractly modified to be "if the voting method would consider a candidate to be better than all other candidates when compared one-on-one, then it must consider that candidate better than all other candidates." Approval Voting and Score Voting, as well as traditional Condorcet methods pass this abstract version of the criterion, while IRV and STAR Voting don't (since they reduce to Plurality in the 2-candidate case and thus would need to always elect the traditional Condorcet winner in order to pass).<ref>[https://rangevoting.org/CondDQ.html The "official" and "unofficial" definitions of "Condorcet" - Warren D. Smith, August 2005]</ref>
 
Line 90 ⟶ 149:
Approval Voting (and thus Score Voting when all voters use only the minimum or maximum score) is equivalent to a traditional Condorcet method where a voter must rank all candidates 1st or last. Score Voting where some voters give some candidates intermediate scores can be treated as Approval Voting using the [[KP transform]], and thus treated as a traditional Condorcet method in the same way as Approval Voting.
 
==Strategic implications==
== Notes ==
 
Every Condorcet method is susceptible to burial in at least some elections, and Condorcet is also incompatible with [[later-no-harm]] and [[later-no-help]]. However, if a method passes the [[informed majority coalition criterion]] so a coordinated majority can always force its outcome, then prefixing a Condorcet step to that method can never increase the proportion of elections where strategy pays off.<ref name="Green-Armytage Tideman Cosman pp. 183–212">{{cite journal | last=Green-Armytage | first=James | last2=Tideman | first2=T. Nicolaus | last3=Cosman | first3=Rafael | title=Statistical evaluation of voting rules | journal=Social Choice and Welfare | publisher=Springer Science and Business Media LLC | volume=46 | issue=1 | date=2015-08-11 | issn=0176-1714 | doi=10.1007/s00355-015-0909-0 | pages=183–212|url=http://jamesgreenarmytage.com/strategy-utility.pdf}}</ref><ref name="Durand Mathieu Noirie 2014">{{cite web | last=Durand | first=François | last2=Mathieu | first2=Fabien | last3=Noirie | first3=Ludovic | title=Making most voting systems meet the Condorcet criterion reduces their manipulability | website=Inria | date=2014-06-17 | url=https://hal.inria.fr/hal-01009134 | access-date=2022-01-12}}</ref>
The Condorcet criterion has been criticized for certain reasons. Here is one [https://www.fairvote.org/why-the-condorcet-criterion-is-less-important-than-it-seems critique] by FairVote, with some analysis:
 
==Criticism==
<blockquote>If there is a Condorcet winner, it means that he or she is preferred to every other candidate – not necessarily liked more than other candidates and not necessarily ready to represent the constituents.</blockquote>
The Condorcet criterion and methods that pass it have been criticized for certain reasons. Some common arguments are:
 
===Operational concerns===
If one candidate is preferred over another, it necessarily means the voter likes that candidate more than the other.
 
*Less [[precinct-summable]] than some other voting methods (because it requires [[pairwise counting]]).
<blockquote>Condorcet winners are centrist by nature, regardless of the preferences of the electorate.</blockquote>
*Harder to understand than other voting methods due to pairwise logic.
 
===Susceptibility to strategy===
Not necessarily. If an electorate is 55% liberal, the Condorcet winner will be liberal, whereas if the electorate is 55% conservative, the CW will be conservative. They may lean towards the center to some degree (if the minority prefers them more than other candidates supported by the majority), but they do shift with regards to the voters' preferences.
 
*Possibly more vulnerable to [[Strategic voting|common-sense strategies]] like [[burial]], due to failing [[later-no-harm]] and [[later-no-help]].<ref name="Woodall-Monotonicity">{{cite journal| title = Monotonicity and single-seat election rules| last = Woodall| first = Douglas R.| journal = Voting matters| volume = 6| pages = 9–14| year = 1996|url=http://www.votingmatters.org.uk/ISSUE6/P4.HTM}}</ref>
<blockquote>Consider an election with three candidates: a strong liberal who commands between 40% to 50% of the vote, a moderate with about 10% to 15%, and a strong conservative between 40% and 50%. By being everyone’s second choice, the moderate will certainly be the Condorcet winner as long as neither of the two more extreme candidates earns a majority of the vote. If the electorate is moderate, then great – the Condorcet winner makes sense. But if the electorate mostly wants something to the left or right of the center, is it still the case that the moderate should always win? Wouldn’t the 80% to 90% of voters who lean clearly to one side prefer that their candidate have a nonzero chance of winning, as opposed to the impossibility of victory under Condorcet methods?</blockquote>
**The Condorcet criterion's implication of [[later-no-harm]] failure may also incentivize [[bullet voting]].
 
*It implies failure of the [[Favorite Betrayal|Favorite Betrayal criterion]] (possibly leading to [[two-party domination]])
The problem with this argument is that if most of the voters prefer something other than the centrist candidate, they are free to rank candidates on both sides above the moderate candidate, which would guarantee the moderate wouldn't be the CW. In other words, if voters indicate they prefer the moderate over the other side, then they shouldn't be surprised if this allows them to get the moderate instead of the one of the other side's candidates as a winner.
*May lead to [[DH3]] failures (frequently elects the worst candidate due to strategic voting) unless the method is constructed to avoid this (e.g. [[Benham's method]]).
 
===Quality of winners===
<blockquote>Looking to Burlington [...] The mayor was vulnerable, but Montroll only secured 22% of first choices and only 29% when the field was reduced to three, basically failing to make the case for his candidacy to enough people. If Montroll had won due to Condorcet voting being in place, the resulting controversy in Burlington would likely have been far louder than the outcry against Kiss’s IRV victory. Having a candidate win after being in last place when the field was reduced to three would have taken a lot of explaining to voters. They might have accepted the results; more likely, they would have challenged them, particularly if they understood that Democrats would suddenly be the dominant party in mayor’s race even when failing to finish in the top two.</blockquote>
 
*The weak centrist argument: Condorcet methods don't take [[strength of preference]] information into account, and thus can't distinguish between a strong consensus candidate and a bland centrist who is inoffensive enough to be everybody's second choice.
This criticism can easily be averted if the voters on either side of the Democrats simply refuse to rank the Democrats above the other side.
**''Rebuttal'': Ranked ballots can't tell the two scenarios apart, so a ranked method that doesn't elect a weak centrist [[center squeeze|won't elect a strong centrist either]].<ref>{{cite web|url=http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2002-November/074157.html|title=Sports and "The Condorcet Mindset"|website=Election-methods mailing list archives|date=2002-11-17|last=Small|first=Alex}}</ref> Electing a strong centrist may be worth the cost of potentially electing a weak centrist. The problem can also be addressed by using a [[rated pairwise preference ballot]].
 
*The Condorcet criterion's preference for consensus winners may lead centrists to win so often that they become near-monopolists, if the political contest takes place on a line (like a left-right spectrum).
'''Alternative definition of "beat" that is claimed to be more consistent with the preferences, intent and wishes of equal-top-ranking voters:'''
**''Rebuttal'': The problem vanishes with multidimensional politics, and thus Condorcet methods reward candidates who break politics out of its one-dimensional mold.<ref>{{cite web|url=http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2003-August/010574.html|title=[EM] Condorcet 2 - The Sequel ( the same people say the same things)|website=Election-methods mailing list archives|date=2003-08-07|last=Small|first=Alex}}</ref>
 
*Non-Condorcet methods (usually referring to [[Score voting]]) may be more [[Smith-efficient]] than actual Condorcet methods.<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://rangevoting.org/CondStratProb.html|title=RangeVoting.org - How Condorcet voting can fail to elect Condorcet Winner|website=rangevoting.org|access-date=2020-05-14}}</ref>
(Argument supporting that claim can be found at the [[Symmetrical ICT]] article.)
**''Rebuttal'': [[:Category:Condorcet-cardinal hybrid methods|Condorcet-cardinal hybrid methods]] are less susceptible to this issue than other Condorcet methods; in the example provided, strategic voters could place their [[approval threshold]] in such a way as to elect the CW.
 
<br />
{{definition|1=
 
===FairVote critique===
(X>Y) means the number of ballots voting X over Y.
 
(Y>X) means the number of ballots voting Y over X.
 
(X=Y)T means the number of ballots voting X and Y at top
 
Here is one [https://www.fairvote.org/why-the-condorcet-criterion-is-less-important-than-it-seems critique] by FairVote, with some analysis/rebuttals:<blockquote>If there is a Condorcet winner, it means that he or she is preferred to every other candidate – not necessarily liked more than other candidates and not necessarily ready to represent the constituents.</blockquote>
(a ballot votes a candidate at top if it doesn't vote anyone over him/her)
 
If one candidate is preferred over another, it necessarily means the voter likes that candidate more than the other.
X beats Y iff (X>Y) > (Y>X) + (X=Y)T
 
<blockquote>Condorcet winners are centrist by nature, regardless of the preferences of the electorate.</blockquote>
}}
 
Not necessarily. If an electorate is 55% liberal, the Condorcet winner will be liberal, whereas if the electorate is 55% conservative, the CW will be conservative. They may lean towards the center to some degree (if the minority prefers them more than other candidates supported by the majority), but they do shift with regards to the voters' preferences.
 
<blockquote>Consider an election with three candidates: a strong liberal who commands between 40% to 50% of the vote, a moderate with about 10% to 15%, and a strong conservative between 40% and 50%. By being everyone’s second choice, the moderate will certainly be the Condorcet winner as long as neither of the two more extreme candidates earns a majority of the vote. If the electorate is moderate, then great – the Condorcet winner makes sense. But if the electorate mostly wants something to the left or right of the center, is it still the case that the moderate should always win? Wouldn’t the 80% to 90% of voters who lean clearly to one side prefer that their candidate have a nonzero chance of winning, as opposed to the impossibility of victory under Condorcet methods?</blockquote>
 
The problem with this argument is that if most of the voters prefer something other than the centrist candidate, they are free to rank candidates on both sides above the moderate candidate, which would guarantee the moderate wouldn't be the CW. In other words, if voters indicate they prefer the moderate over the other side, then they shouldn't be surprised if this allows them to get the moderate instead of the one of the other side's candidates as a winner.
 
<blockquote>Looking to Burlington [...] The mayor was vulnerable, but Montroll only secured 22% of first choices and only 29% when the field was reduced to three, basically failing to make the case for his candidacy to enough people. If Montroll had won due to Condorcet voting being in place, the resulting controversy in Burlington would likely have been far louder than the outcry against Kiss’s IRV victory. Having a candidate win after being in last place when the field was reduced to three would have taken a lot of explaining to voters. They might have accepted the results; more likely, they would have challenged them, particularly if they understood that Democrats would suddenly be the dominant party in mayor’s race even when failing to finish in the top two.</blockquote>
 
This criticism can easily be averted if the voters on either side of the Democrats simply refuse to rank the Democrats above the other side..
 
==Notes==
 
It is rather common for pollsters to do head-to-head matchup polling to see who is likely to win in an [[FPTP]] general election. Condorcet polling can be done in a similar way, except more efficiently, by allowing polled voters to rank or rate the candidates.<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Potthoff|first=Richard F.|date=2011-07-01|title=Condorcet Polling|url=https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-010-9646-1|journal=Public Choice|language=en|volume=148|issue=1|pages=67–86|doi=10.1007/s11127-010-9646-1|issn=1573-7101}}</ref>
 
One strategy common to most Condorcet methods is to prevent a candidate from being a Condorcet winner by [[burying]] them (giving them a pairwise defeat against another candidate).
 
===Alternative definitions===
With this alternative definition of "beat", [[FBC]] and the Condorcet Criterion are compatible.
The [[tied at the top]] rule redefines the Condorcet beat relation so that methods using it can pass Condorcet whenever there are no equal-rank, and in addition passes the [[favorite betrayal criterion]]. Doing so in effect trades some Condorcet winner compliance for FBC compliance.
 
It has been recently argued that the definition of the verb "beat" should be regarded as external to the Condorcet Criterion...and that "beat should be defined in a way that interprets equal-top ranking consistent with the actual preferences, intent and wishes of the equal-top-ranking voters. When such a definition of "beat" is used in the Condorcet Criterion definition, then the Condorcet Criterion is compatible with [[FBC]], and there are Condorcet methods that pass [[FBC]]. Discussion and arguments on that matter can be found at the [[Symmetrical ICT]] article.
[[Category:Voting system criteria]]
 
==Outside of voting theory==
Analogues to the Condorcet criterion have been proposed in non-voting contexts; it appears in many places when discussing how to aggregate ranked information. It has been used to discuss search engine rankings <ref name="Dwork Kumar Naor Sivakumar 2001 p. ">{{cite conference | last=Dwork | first=Cynthia | last2=Kumar | first2=Ravi | last3=Naor | first3=Moni | last4=Sivakumar | first4=D. | title=Rank aggregation methods for the Web | publisher=ACM | publication-place=New York, NY, USA | year=2001 | doi=10.1145/371920.372165 | url=http://www.eecs.harvard.edu/~michaelm/CS222/rank.pdf}}</ref> and metasearch<ref name="Montague Aslam 2002 p. ">{{cite conference | last=Montague | first=Mark | last2=Aslam | first2=Javed A. | title=Condorcet fusion for improved retrieval | publisher=ACM | publication-place=New York, NY, USA | date=2002-11-04 | doi=10.1145/584792.584881 | url=http://www.ccs.neu.edu/home/jaa/IS4200.10X1/resources/condorcet.pdf}}</ref>. The concept of a [[Smith set ranking]] (which is sometimes referred to as the "extended/generalised Condorcet criterion") helps structure how the ranking of all options should be, rather than only the winner.
 
==References==