Majority Judgment: Difference between revisions

Fix claim that MJ passes reversal symmetry (it fails it). Add section referring to Fabre's variant rules.
(Add references from Wikipedia, and French video describing using MJ to elect the President of France. Split notes into footnotes and references.)
(Fix claim that MJ passes reversal symmetry (it fails it). Add section referring to Fabre's variant rules.)
Line 11:
 
== Satisfied and failed criteria ==
Majority Judgment voting satisfies the [[Majority criterion for rated ballots|majority criterion for rated ballots]], and also a weak form of the [[mutual majority criterion]] (a majority giving only and all of their preferred candidates perfect grades will win), the [[monotonicity criterion]], [[reversal symmetry]], and [[later-no-harm|later-no-help]]. Assuming that ratings are given independently of other candidates, it satisfies the [[independence of clones criterion]] and the [[independence of irrelevant alternatives|independence of irrelevant alternatives criterion]]<ref>Badinski and Laraki, ''Majority Judgment'', p. 217</ref> - although this latter criterion is incompatible with the majority criterion if voters shift their judgments in order to express their [[preferential voting|preferences]] between the available candidates.
 
It fails the [[Condorcet criterion]],<ref group="nb">Strategically in the [[strong Nash equilibrium]], MJ passes the Condorcet criterion.</ref> [[later-no-harm]],<ref group="nb">MJ provides a weaker guarantee similar to LNH: rating another candidate at or below your preferred winner's median rating (as opposed to your own rating for the winner) cannot harm the winner.</ref> [[Consistency criterion|consistency]], the [[Condorcet method|Condorcet loser criterion]],<ref group="nb">Nevertheless, it passes a slightly weakened version, the majority condorcet loser criterion, in which all defeats are by an absolute majority (for instance, if there aren't equal rankings).</ref> and the [[participation criterion]].<ref group="nb">It can only fail the participation criterion when, among other conditions, the new ballot rates both of the candidates in question on the same side of the winning median, and the prior distribution of ratings is more sharply-peaked or irregular for one of the candidates.</ref> It also fails the ranked or preferential [[majority criterion]], which is incompatible with the passed criterion [[independence of irrelevant alternatives]], and [[reversal symmetry]].
 
==Example application==
Line 114:
</table>
 
The median rating for Nashville and ChatanoogaChattanooga is "Good"; for Knoxville, "Fair"; and for Memphis, "Poor". Nashville and ChatanoogaChattanooga are tied, so "Good" ratings have to be removed from both, until their medians become different. After removing 16% "Good" ratings from the votes of each, the sorted ratings are now:
 
<table>
Line 179:
</table>
 
ChatanoogaChattanooga now has the same number of "Fair" ratings as "Good" and "Excellent" combined, so its median is rounded down to "Fair", while Nashville's median remains at "Good"<ref group="nb">After removal, ChatanoogaChattanooga has 42% of the initial electorate at "Fair", 27% "Good", and 15% "Excellent", while Nashville has 32% "Fair", 26% "Good", and 26% "Excellent"</ref> and so '''Nashville''', the capital in real life, wins.
 
If voters from Knoxville and Chattanooga were to rate Nashville as "Poor" and/or both sets of voters were to rate Chattanooga as "Excellent", in an attempt to make their preferred candidate ChatanoogaChattanooga win, the winner would still be Nashville.
 
==Variants==
 
Variants of majority judgment have been described. Fabre considers three: the typical judgment, usual judgment, and central judgment.<ref name="Fabre20">{{Cite journal |first=Adrien |last=Fabre |title=Tie-breaking the Highest Median: Alternatives to the Majority Judgment |journal=[[Social Choice and Welfare]] |year=2020 |volume=56 |pages=101–124 |url=https://github.com/bixiou/highest_median/raw/master/Tie-breaking%20Highest%20Median%20-%20Fabre%202019.pdf |doi=10.1007/s00355-020-01269-9|issn=0176-1714}}</ref>. He argues that all of these are less sensitive to noise than the majority judgment, with the usual judgment being the most robust, though the calculation that determines the winner is more complex.
 
==See also==
1,196

edits