Majority Judgment

Revision as of 15:43, 28 June 2011 by 187.143.6.208 (talk) (from wp)
(diff) ← Older revision | Latest revision (diff) | Newer revision → (diff)

Majority Judgment is a single-winner voting system proposed by Michel Balinski and Rida Laraki. Voters freely grade each candidate in one of several named ranks, for instance from "excellent" to "bad", and the candidate with the highest median grade is the winner. If more than one candidate has the same median grade, a tiebreaker is used which sees how "broad" that median grade is. It can be considered as a form of Bucklin voting which allows equal ranks.

Voting process

Voters are allowed rated ballots, on which they may assign a grade or judgement to each candidate. Badinski and Laraki suggest six grading levels, from "Excellent" to "To Reject". Multiple candidates may be given the same grade if the voter desires.

The median grade for each candidate is found, for instance by sorting their list of grades and finding the middle one. If the middle falls between two different grades, the lower of the two is used.

The candidate with the highest median grade wins. If several candidates share the higest median grade, all other candidates are eliminated. Then, one copy of that grade is removed from each remaining candidate's list of grades, and the new median is found, until an unambiguous winner is found.

Satisfied and failed criteria

Majority Judgment voting satisfies the majority criterion for rated ballots, the mutual majority criterion, the monotonicity criterion, reversal symmetry, and later-no-help. Assuming that ratings are given independently of other candidates, it satisfies the independence of clones criterion and the independence of irrelevant alternatives criterion[1] - although this latter criterion is incompatible with the majority criterion if voters shift their judgments in order to express their preferences between the available candidates.

It fails the Condorcet criterion,[2] later-no-harm,[3] consistency, the Condorcet loser criterion,[4] and the participation criterion.[5] It also fails the ranked or preferential majority criterion, which is incompatible with the passed criterion independence of irrelevant alternatives.

Example application

 
Tennessee's four cities are spread throughout the state

Imagine that Tennessee is having an election on the location of its capital. The population of Tennessee is concentrated around its four major cities, which are spread throughout the state. For this example, suppose that the entire electorate lives in these four cities, and that everyone wants to live as near the capital as possible.

The candidates for the capital are:

  • Memphis, the state's largest city, with 42% of the voters, but located far from the other cities
  • Nashville, with 26% of the voters, near the center of Tennessee
  • Knoxville, with 17% of the voters
  • Chattanooga, with 15% of the voters

The preferences of the voters would be divided like this:

42% of voters
(close to Memphis)
26% of voters
(close to Nashville)
15% of voters
(close to Chattanooga)
17% of voters
(close to Knoxville)
  1. Memphis
  2. Nashville
  3. Chattanooga
  4. Knoxville
  1. Nashville
  2. Chattanooga
  3. Knoxville
  4. Memphis
  1. Chattanooga
  2. Knoxville
  3. Nashville
  4. Memphis
  1. Knoxville
  2. Chattanooga
  3. Nashville
  4. Memphis

If there were four ratings named "Excellent", "Good", "Fair", and "Poor", and each voter assigned four different ratings to the four cities, then the sorted scores would be as follows:


City
  \/ Median point
Nashville
 
Chattanooga
 
Knoxville
 
Memphis
 
   
 
     Exellent      Good      Fair      Poor    

The medians for Nashville and Chatanooga would be "Good"; for Knoxville, "Fair"; and for Memphis, "Poor". Nashville and Chatanooga are tied, so "Good" ratings would be removed from both. After removing 16% of the votes from each, Chatanooga's median would round down to "Fair", while Nashville would remain at "Good"[6] and so Nashville would win.

City
  \/ Median point
Nashville
   
Chattanooga
 
   
 
     Removed ratings (sorted to both ends evenly for easy comparison of medians with above).  

See also

Notes

  1. Badinski and Laraki, Majority Judgment, p. 217
  2. Strategically in the strong Nash equilibrium, MJ passes the Condorcet criterion.
  3. MJ provides a weaker guarantee similar to LNH: rating another candidate at or below your preferred winner's median rating (as opposed to your own rating for the winner) cannot harm the winner.
  4. Nevertheless, it passes a slightly weakened version, the majority condorcet loser criterion, in which all defeats are by an absolute majority (for instance, if there aren't equal rankings).
  5. It can only fail the participation criterion when, among other conditions, the new ballot rates both of the candidates in question on the same side of the winning median, and the prior distribution of ratings is more sharply-peaked or irregular for one of the candidates.
  6. After removal, Chatanooga would have 42% of the initial electorate at "Fair", 27% "Good", and 15% "Excellent", while Nashville would have 32% "Fair", 26% "Good", and 26% "Excellent"

References

  • Balinski, Michel, and Laraki, Rida (2010). Majority Judgment: Measuring, Ranking, and Electing, MIT Press