Mutual majority criterion: Difference between revisions

No edit summary
(17 intermediate revisions by 3 users not shown)
Line 1:
{{wikipedia}}
The '''Mutualmutual majority criterion''' is a criterion for evaluating [[voting system]]s. Most simply, it can be thought of as requiring that whenever a [[majority]] of voters prefer a set of candidates (often candidates from the same political party) above all others (i.e. when choosing among ice cream flavors, a majority of voters are split between several variants of chocolate ice cream, but agree that any of the chocolate-type flavors are better than any of the other ice cream flavors), someone from that set must win (i.e. one of the chocolate-type flavors must win). It is the single-winner case of Droop-[[Proportionality for Solid Coalitions]].
 
It is an extension of (and also implies) the [[Majority criterion|majority criterion]] for sets of candidates. Thus, it is often called the '''Majority criterion for [[Solid coalition|solid coalitions]].'''
 
== NotesExample ==
The mutual majority criterion is implied by the [[Smith criterion]].
 
 
Example for candidates A, B, C, D and E (scores are shown for each candidate, with the implicit ranked preferences in parentheses, and the unscored candidates assumed to be ranked last):<blockquote>17 A:10 B:9 C:8 (A>B>C >D=E)
Line 12 ⟶ 14:
 
49 D:10 E:10 (D>E >A=B=C)</blockquote>A, B, and C are preferred by a mutual majority, because a group of 52 voters (out of 100), an absolute majority, scored all of them higher than (preferred them over) all other candidates (D and E). So the mutual majority criterion requires that one of A, B, and C win the election.
 
== Complying and non-complying methods ==
 
; Systems which pass
:[[Baldwin's method|Borda-Elimination]], [[Bucklin voting|Bucklin]], [[Coombs]], [[IRV]], [[Kemeny-Young]], [[Nanson's (original)method]], [[Raynaud|Pairwise-Elimination]], [[Ranked Pairs]], [[Schulze method|Schulze]], [[Smith//Minimax|Smith//Minmax]], [[Descending Solid Coalitions]], [[Majority Choice Approval]], any [[:Category:Smith-efficient Condorcet methods|Smith-efficient Condorcet method]], most [[:Category:Condorcet-IRV hybrid methods|Condorcet-IRV hybrid methods]]
; Systems which fail
: most [[Cardinal voting|rated methods]] (such as [[Approval voting]], [[Score|Score voting]], and [[STAR|STAR voting]]), [[Black]], [[Borda]], [[Dodgson]], [[Minmax]], [[Sum of Defeats]]
 
== Alternative Definitions ==
It can be stated as follows:
It can be stated as follows:{{definition|If there is a majority of voters for which it is true that they all rank a set of candidates above all others, then one of these candidates must win.}}
 
{{definition|A mutual majority (MM) is a set of voters comprising a majority of the voters, who all prefer some same set of candidates to all of the other candidates. That set of candidates is their MM-preferred set.
A generalized form that also encompasses [[Rated voting|rated voting]] methods: <blockquote>If a majority of voters unanimously vote a given set of candidates above a given rating or ranking, and all other candidates below that rating or ranking, then the winner must be from that set.</blockquote>Note that the logical implication of the mutual majority criterion is that a candidate from the '''smallest''' set of candidates preferred by the same absolute majority of voters over all others must win; this is because if, for example, 51 voters prefer A over B, and B over C, with the other 49 voters preferring C, then not only is (A, B) a set of candidates preferred by an absolute majority over all others (C), but candidate A is also a candidate preferred by an absolute majority over all others (B and C), and therefore A must win in order to satisfy the criterion.
If a MM vote sincerely, then the winner should come from their MM-preferred set.
A voter votes sincerely if s/he doesn't vote an unfelt preference, or fail to vote a felt preference that the balloting system in use would have allowed hir to vote in addition to the preferences that she actually does vote.
To vote an unfelt preference is to vote X over Y if you prefer X to Y.
To vote an unfelt preference is to vote X over Y if you don't prefer X to Y.}}
 
or more simply,
It is sometimes simply (and confusingly) called the '''Majority criterion.'''
 
It can be stated as follows:{{definition|If there is a majority of voters for which it is true that they all rank a set of candidates above all others, then one of these candidates must win.}}
== Notes ==
 
Voting methods which pass the majority criterion but not the mutual majority criterion (some ranked methods fall under this category, notably [[FPTP]]) possess a spoiler effect, since if all but one candidate in the mutual majority drops out, the remaining candidate in the mutual majority is guaranteed to win, whereas if nobody had dropped out, a candidate not in the mutual majority might have won.
A generalized form that also encompasses [[Rated voting|rated voting]] methods: {{definition|If a majority of voters unanimously vote a given set of candidates above a given rating or ranking, and all other candidates below that rating or ranking, then the winner must be from that set.}}
 
A generalized form that also encompasses [[Rated voting|rated voting]] methods: <blockquote>If a majority of voters unanimously vote a given set of candidates above a given rating or ranking, and all other candidates below that rating or ranking, then the winner must be from that set.</blockquote>Note that the logical implication of the mutual majority criterion is that a candidate from the '''smallest''' set of candidates preferred by the same absolute majority of voters over all others must win; this is because if, for example, 51 voters prefer A over B, and B over C, with the other 49 voters preferring C, then not only is (A, B) a set of candidates preferred by an absolute majority over all others (C), but candidate A is also a candidate preferred by an absolute majority over all others (B and C), and therefore A must win in order to satisfy the criterion.
 
It is sometimes simply (and confusingly) called the '''Majority criterion.''' This usage is due to Woodall.<ref name="Woodall 1994 Properties">{{cite journal | last=Woodall |first=D. |title=Properties of preferential election rules | journal=Voting matters | issue=3 | pages=8–15 | year=1994 | url=http://www.votingmatters.org.uk/ISSUE3/P5.HTM}}</ref>
 
== Related forms of the criterion ==
 
=== Stronger forms ===
The mutual majority criterion is implied by the [[dominant mutual third]] property, which itself is implied by the [[Smith criterion]].
 
=== Weaker forms ===
By analogy to the [[majority criterion for rated ballots]], one could design a mutual majority criterion for rated ballots, which would be the mutual majority criterion with the requirement that each voter in the majority give at least one candidate in the mutual majority-preferred set of candidates a perfect (maximal) score. An even weaker criterion along these lines would be that the mutual majority must give everyone they prefer a perfect score; [[Majority Judgment]] passes this.
 
 
 
<br />
== Notes ==
 
Voting methods which pass the majority criterion but not the mutual majority criterion (some ranked methods fall under this category, notably [[FPTP]]) possess a spoiler effect, since if all but one candidate in the mutual majority drops out, the remaining candidate in the mutual majority is guaranteed to win, whereas if nobody had dropped out, a candidate not in the mutual majority might have won. This is also why [[:Category:Sequential loser-elimination methods|Sequential loser-elimination methods]] whose base methods pass the majority criterion pass the mutual majority criterion.
 
All [[Condorcet methods]] pass mutual majority when there is a [[Condorcet winner]], since if there is a mutual majority set, all candidates in it pairwise beat all candidates not in it by virtue of being preferred by an absolute majority; since the CW isn't pairwise beaten by anyone, they must be in the set. [[Smith-efficient]] [[Condorcet methods]] always pass mutual majority.
 
In contrast to the [[dominant mutual third]] set, a mutual majority set is always also a dominant mutual majority set. Every coalition that has majority support also pairwise beats the rest of the candidates, but that is not true of all coalitions supported by more than 1/3 of the voters.
 
=== Dominant mutual plurality criterion ===
The mutual majority criterion doesn't apply to situations where there are large "sides" if enough voters are indifferent to the large sides. Example: <blockquote>51 A>C
 
Line 46 ⟶ 84:
30: B
 
35: C2>B</blockquote>and B is eliminated first, despite pairwise dominating everyone else (i.e. being the [[Condorcet winner]]). This is an example of the [[Center squeeze]] effect.
 
=== Semi-mutual majority ===
If there are some losing candidates ranked above the mutual majority set of candidates by some voters in the majority, this voids the criterion guarantee. Example: <blockquote>26 A>B
 
25 B
 
49 C</blockquote>Despite B being preferred by an absolute majority over C, and the only candidate preferred by any voters in that absolute majority over or equally to B being A (with no voters in the majority preferring anyone over A), the mutual majority criterion doesn't guarantee that either A or B must win. It has been argued that to avoid the [[Chicken dilemma]], C must win here (and C would win in some mutual majority-passing methods, such as [[IRV]], which is often claimed to resist the chicken dilemma), but methods that do so have a spoiler effect, since if A drops out, B must win by the majority (and thus mutual majority) criterion. All major [[:Category:Defeat-dropping Condorcet methods|defeat-dropping Condorcet methods]] elect B here, since they have the weakest pairwise defeat.
 
=== Independence of mutual majority-dominated alternatives ===
Similar to [[Independence of Smith-dominated Alternatives]], a "independence of mutual majority-dominated alternatives" criterion could be envisioned.
 
Both [[instant-runoff voting]] and [[Descending Acquiescing Coalitions]] fail this criterion, as can be shown by [[Left, Center, Right]] scenarios when y+z also constitutes a majority.
 
For instance:
 
{{ballots|
4: L>C>R
3: R>C>L
2: C>L>R}}
 
The smallest mutual majority set is {L, C}, and C beats L pairwise, so in any election where those two candidates are the only one in the running, C wins. However, [[IRV]] first eliminates C and then L beats R. [[DAC]] first excludes R from the set of viable candidates (because the {L, C} coalition is the largest). Then L has the greatest first preference count of the two and thus wins.
 
=== Finding the mutual majority set ===
 
==== Pairwise counting ====
Note that the mutual majority set is a pairwise-dominating set (every candidate in it [[pairwise]] beats every candidate not in it). So one way to find it would be to find the [[Smith set ranking]], and then look for the smallest group of candidates highest in the Smith ranking who are preferred by a mutual majority, if there is one.
 
The smallest mutual majority set can be found in part by looking for the [[Smith set]], because the Smith set is always a subset of the mutual majority set when one exists, and then adding in candidates into the mutual majority set who are preferred by enough of the voters who helped the candidates in the Smith set beat other candidates to constitute a mutual majority. Example:
 
35 A>B
 
35 B>A
 
30 C>B
 
The Smith set is just B here. When looking at the 70 voters who helped B beat C and the 65 for B>A, it's clear that a majority of them prefer A over C, and that an absolute majority of voters prefer either A or B over C. So the smallest mutual majority set is A and B.
 
==== Bucklin approach ====
 
 
An alternative way to find the smallest mutual majority set would be to use a modified version of [[Bucklin voting]]: for each voter, assume they "approve" all of their 1st choices. Find the ballot which approves the most candidates; for each other ballot, until it approves as many candidates as this "most-approvals" ballot, the most-approvals ballot should be prevented from approving any more candidates. Once a ballot approves as many or more candidates than the most-approvals ballot, it should be considered the most-approvals ballot instead, and likewise, it should stop approving additional candidates. For each ballot that is not a most-approvals ballot, approve all candidates at the next consecutive rank where candidates haven't been approved yet for that ballot. Do this until some candidate(s) are approved by a majority of voters, and then check if all ballots approving each majority-approved candidate do not approve anyone else. If so, then the majority-approved candidates are the smallest mutual majority set, but if not, then there is no smallest mutual majority set. For example:<blockquote>17 A>B>C
 
17 A=B>C
 
17 C>A>B
 
49 D>E>F</blockquote>34 voters approve A as their 1st choice, 17 B, 17 C, and 49 D. The 17 A=B voters approve both A and B, two candidates, making them the most-approvals voters currently, so they are not allowed to approve any more candidates for now. Adding in the next rank, 17 voters now approve B as their 2nd choice, 17 A, and 49 E. Now 51 voters approve A, so check whether they are a mutual majority. In this case, the only candidates any of the 51 voters prefer more than or equally to A are B and C; it is seen that all 51 voters prefer any of A, B, or C over all other candidates (D, E, and F), so ABC is the smallest mutual majority set.     
 
==References==
<references />
 
By analogy to the majority criterion for rated ballots, one could design a mutual majority criterion for rated ballots, which would be the mutual majority criterion with the requirement that each voter in the majority give at least one candidate in the mutual majority-preferred set of candidates a perfect (maximal) score.
[[Category:Voting system criteria]]
[[Category:Majority–minority relations]]