Jump to content

Arrow's impossibility theorem: Difference between revisions

Line 34:
</ref><ref>{{Cite web| title = Podcast 2012-10-06: Interview with Nobel Laureate Dr. Kenneth Arrow| work = The Center for Election Science| accessdate = 2020-03-20| date = 2015-05-25| url = https://www.electionscience.org/commentary-analysis/voting-theory-podcast-2012-10-06-interview-with-nobel-laureate-dr-kenneth-arrow/|quote=CES: Now, you mention that your theorem applies to preferential systems or ranking systems. Dr. Arrow: Yes CES: But the system that you’re just referring to, Approval Voting, falls within a class called cardinal systems. So not within ranking systems. Dr. Arrow: And as I said, that in effect implies more information.}}</ref> The typical example is [[score voting]] but there are also several [[Multi-Member System |multi-winner systems]]{{clarify}} which purport to pass all three of Arrow's original criteria. Additionally, there are cardinal systems which do not pass all criteria, but this is not due to Arrow's theorem; for example [[Ebert's Method]] fails [[Monotonicity]].
 
=== Benefits ===
However, note that one of the assumptions used in Arrow's Theorem is that voters do not change their preferences on a given set of candidates regardless of whether candidates not in the set are running or not running. If even a single voter [[Normalization|normalizes]] their rated ballot or otherwise deviates from this assumption, it fails. Example:<blockquote>1: A:10 B:6 C:0
 
There are two main "benefits" that come from evading Arrow's theorem: when candidates enter or drop out of the race, this doesn't impact the choice between the remaining candidates, and when voters are trying to impact the race between a certain set of candidates, they need only alter the portions of their ballot that show their preferences among that set of candidates.
 
However, note that to obtain the first benefit, one of the assumptions used in Arrow's Theorem is that voters do not change their preferences on a given set of candidates regardless of whether candidates not in the set are running or not running. If even a single voter [[Normalization|normalizes]] their rated ballot or otherwise deviates from this assumption, it fails. Example:<blockquote>1: A:10 B:6 C:0
 
1: B:10 C:4 A:0
Line 44 ⟶ 48:
1: A:10 B:0</blockquote>Scores are A 20, B 10, and now A wins in Score voting. This example uses the standard [[Condorcet paradox]] but presented in rated form.
 
=== Caveats ===
 
 
However, subsequent social choice theorists have expanded on Arrow's central insight, and applied his ideas more broadly. For example, the [[Gibbard-Satterthwaite theorem]] (published in 1973) holds that any deterministic process of collective decision making with multiple options will have some level of [[strategic voting]]. As a result of this much of the work of social choice theorists is to find out what types of [[strategic voting]] a system is susceptible to and the level of susceptibility for each. For example [[Single Member system | Single Member systems]] are not susceptible to [[Free riding]].
Cookies help us deliver our services. By using our services, you agree to our use of cookies.