3-2-1 voting: Difference between revisions

imported>Homunq
No edit summary
 
(22 intermediate revisions by 5 users not shown)
Line 1:
In '''3-2-1 voting''', voters may rate each candidate “Good”, “OK”, or “Bad”. It(Alternately, they may rate one candidate "Good" and leave the rest blank, which will cause the rest of their ballot to be filled in automatically.[[#Footnote_.C2.B9:_Blank_ratings|¹]]) The tallying process has three steps:
 
* Find '''3 Semifinalistssemifinalists''': the candidates with the '''most “good”''' ratings. [[#Footnote_.C2.B2:_rules_for_the_third_semifinalist|²]]
* Find '''2 Finalistsfinalists''': the semifinalists with the '''fewest "bad"''' ratings.
* Find '''1 winner''': the finalist who is rated '''above the other''' on more ballots (like a virtual runoff).
 
== Motivation for each step ==
There are two extra qualifications for semifinalists: their "good" ratings should be more than anyone else in their party (that is, only one semifinalist per party), and at least 15% of the electorate. Usually all three semifinalists will easily pass these qualifications naturally, but if only 2 of them do, you can just treat them as finalists and skip step 2.
 
The first qualification to win is that a significant number of people take you seriously and support you.
== Blank ratings ==
 
The second qualification is that you're not opposed by a majority; ideally, opposed by as few as possible.
There are two ways to handle blank ratings: "Undelegated", which does its best to infer voter intentions; and "delegated", which makes voting easier for voters by letting them choose to give some of their voting power to their favorite candidate. "Delegated" is suggested unless there are reasons against it.
 
Between the two candidates who pass those two filters, it's just "majority rules", among voters who made some distinction. Putting this step at the end minimizes the incentives for voters to strategically exaggerate distinctions.
=== Undelegated 3-2-1 ===
 
These three steps are each important. They have to come in that order: pairwise has to come last because it only works with a pair, and putting the "fewest bad" step first would risk leaving only inoffensive nonentities.
For voters who do not explicitly use the "Bad" rating, blank ratings count as "bad". For those who do use "bad", blank ratings count as "OK", except that in step 3 they count as lower than an explicit "OK".
 
It is impossible to strategically affect the outcome of the first two stages without risking losing your voice in the third stage. Probably the most safe and effective thing is to just vote honestly.
=== Delegated 3-2-1 ===
 
== Footnote ¹: Blank ratings ==
In this method, each candidate can pre-rate other candidates "OK", "conditionally OK", or "bad". If they do not explicitly pre-rate, they are considered to rate all others "conditionally OK". Once all ratings have been submitted, all "conditionally OK" ratings are turned to "Bad" if the rating coming the other way is "Bad", and to "OK" otherwise. Candidate ratings are public information.
 
There are two ways to handle blank ratings: "Undelegated", which does its best to infer voter intentions; and "delegatedDelegated", which makes voting easier for voters by letting them choose to give some of their voting power to their favorite candidate; and "Undelegated", which does its best to infer voter intentions directly. "Delegated" is suggested unless there are reasons against it.
When a voter leaves a candidate X blank/unrated, X receives the lowest rating that they got from any candidate that voter rated "Good". So if the voter had rated candidates A and B "good", and both A and B rated X as "OK", then X would get an "OK" from that voter; while if either A and/or B had rated X as "Bad", then X would get a "Bad" from that voter.
 
=== TiebreakerDelegated 3-2-1 ===
 
In this method, each candidate can pre-rate other candidates "OK", "conditionally OK", or "bad". If they do not explicitly pre-rate, they are considered to pre-rate all others "conditionally OK". Once all pre-ratings have been submitted, all "conditionally OK" pre-ratings are turned to "Bad" if the pre-rating coming from the other waycandidate is "Bad", and to "OK" otherwise. For example, if candidate A pre-rates candidate B "conditionally OK" and B pre-rates A "bad", A's pre-rating of B turns to "bad"; if A pre-rates B "conditionally OK" and B pre-rates A "OK" or "conditionally OK", A's pre-rating of B turns to "OK". Candidate pre-ratings are public information.
In all cases, ties are broken by score, with each "Good" counting as 2 points and each "OK" counting as 1. If two candidates are tied in score as well (highly unlikely), the tie is broken randomly.
 
When a voter leaves a candidate X blank/unrated, and rates exactly one other candidate Y as "Good", that counts as rating X as "OK" if Y pre-rated X "OK". Otherwise, it counts as rating X "Bad". Implicit OKs in this sense are counted as lower than explicit OKs in the final round of the tally.
== Motivation for each step ==
 
For example, if I rated only Aurelio "good" and left Beth and Chung blank; and Aurelio pre-rated Beth as "OK" and Chung as "Bad", then I'd count as giving those ratings. If I'd also rated Dana "good", then my blank rating for Beth would count as "bad", no matter what Dana and Aurelio said.
Step 1: A winner should have strong support; at least some voters who have paid attention and are enthusiastic. But if you keep fewer than 3 at this stage, you'd risk prematurely eliminating a centrist and leaving only the two extremes.
 
=== Undelegated 3-2-1 ===
Step 2: This allows a majority of the electorate to have a veto on any candidate. Also, candidates that are eliminated here would usually have little chance in step 3 anyway.
 
For voters who do not explicitly use the "Bad" rating, blank ratings count as "bad". For those who do use "bad", blank ratings count as "OK", except that in step 3 they count as lower than an explicit "OK".
Step 3: This is like a runoff between the two strongest candidates. If you know which two candidates will be finalists, you have no incentive not to rank them honestly, and everybody who made a distinction between them gets equal voting power.
 
== Footnote ²: rules for the third semifinalist ==
== Properties ==
 
There are two extra qualifications when choosing the third (weakest) semifinalist. First, they must not be of the same party as both of the other two; if they are, skip to the next-highest "good" ratings. This prevents one party from winning simply by controlling all three semifinalist slots (the "clone candidate" problem). Second, they must have at least half as many "good" ratings as the first (strongest) semifinalist. If they don't, then skip step 2 entirely and make both semifinalists directly into finalists. This prevents a relatively unknown "also-ran" from winning an election with two dominant, highly-polarized candidates (the "dark horse" problem). A third candidate can win, but only by getting appreciable support.
This method satisfies the [[Majority criterion]]; the [[Condorcet loser criterion]]; [[monotonicity]]; and [[local independence of irrelevant alternatives]].
 
(Note: both of these rules deal with problems that are likely to be relatively rare, and that even if they occur, would often but not always be minor. Thus, though they are definitely recommended in cases where 3-2-1 voting is used on an ongoing basis, they are optional for one-off elections. Also, it might be possible to prevent these problems with other versions of these rules. For instance, the clone candidate problem could be avoided by using a proportional approval system on the "good" votes to pick the top 3, and the dark horse problem could be avoided by a hard minimum threshold such as 15% on "good" votes. The rules in the previous paragraph are suggested as a good compromise between simple and robust, but depending on circumstances one might choose a different compromise.)
It satisfies the [[mutual majority criterion]] as long as any member of the mutual majority set of candidates is among the 3 semifinalists. In practice, this is almost guaranteed to be the case.
 
== Tiebreaker ==
Steps 1 and 3 satisfy the [[later no-harm criterion]]. Thus, the only strategic reason not to add any "OK" ratings would be if your favorite was one of the two most-rejected semifinalists but also was able to beat the least-rejected semifinalist in step 3. This combination of weak and strong is unlikely to happen in real life, and even less likely to be predictable enough a priori to be a basis for strategy.
 
In all cases, ties are broken by score, with each "Good" counting as 2 points and each "OK" counting as 1. If two candidates are tied in score as well (highly unlikely), the tie is broken randomly.
This method fails the [[favorite betrayal criterion]], in that in steps 1 or 2 it could in theory be necessary to rate your favorite below "Good" in order to leave room for a more-viable compromise candidate to be a semifinalist or finalist. However, in order for that to be a worthwhile strategy, the compromise would have to do better in a pairwise race against the other finalist, but have a worse chance of becoming a semifinalist or finalist under your honest vote. This combination of strength in one context and weakness in another is akin to a Condorcet cycle, and like such cycles, it may be rare in real-world elections, and even rarer that it is predictable enough a priori to make a favorite-betrayal strategy feasible.
 
In terms of summability, this can be done in one of two ways. They method can work with one count that is O(N²) summable, or with two consecutive tallies that are each O(N) summable (one for "3-2" and the second for "1"). The latter could make this feasible to run even on older ballot machines; though full counts of the second step might involve some configuration and a couple of passes over the ballots, in many cases the "3-2" tallies would make it obvious who wins the "1" step, so voters would not have to be kept in suspense as the second step proceeded.
 
== Examples ==
Line 49 ⟶ 47:
=== Tennessee capital (center squeeze) ===
 
{{Tenn voting example}}
{{Tenn_voting_example}}
 
This leads to the following outcome:
Line 154 ⟶ 152:
 
This shows a "chicken dilemma" between the felines (Lions and Tigers); together, they can beat Bulldogs, but separately they can't. In 3-2-1, as in almost any voting methods which successfully elect Nashville in the example above, it is possible for the Lions voters to win by strategically rating Tigers as "bad". However, it would take at least 20 of the 25 Lions voters to accomplish this; any fewer, and Tigers would still win. Thus, unlike many voting methods, as long as each Lions voter expects even a third of other Lions voters to vote honestly, there is no incentive for them to "defect" individually.
 
== Properties ==
 
This method satisfies the [[Majority criterion]]; the [[Condorcet loser criterion]]; [[monotonicity]]; and [[local independence of irrelevant alternatives]].
 
It satisfies the [[mutual majority criterion]] as long as any member of the mutual majority set of candidates is among the 3 semifinalists. In practice, this is almost guaranteed to be the case.
 
Steps 1 and 3 satisfy the [[later no-harm criterion]]. Thus, the only strategic reason not to add any "OK" ratings would be if your favorite was one of the two most-rejected semifinalists but also was able to beat the least-rejected semifinalist in step 3. This combination of weak and strong is unlikely to happen in real life, and even less likely to be predictable enough a priori to be a basis for strategy.
 
This method fails the [[favorite betrayal criterion]], in that in steps 1 or 2 it could, in theory, be necessary to rate your favorite below "Good" in order to leave room for a more-viable compromise candidate to be a semifinalist or finalist. However, in order for that to be a worthwhile strategy, the compromise would have to do better in a pairwise race against the other finalist, but have a worse chance of becoming a semifinalist or finalist under your honest vote. This combination of strength in one context and weakness in another is akin to a Condorcet cycle, and [[w:Condorcet_paradox#Likelihood_of_the_paradox|like such cycles, it may be rare in real-world elections]], and even rarer that it is predictable enough a priori to make a favorite-betrayal strategy feasible.
 
In terms of summability, this can be done in one of two ways. TheyThe method can work with one count that is O(N²) summable, or with two consecutive tallies that are each O(N) summable (one for "3-2" and the second for "1"). The latter could make this feasible to run even on older ballot machines; though full counts of the second step might involve some configuration and a couple of passes over the ballots, in many cases the "3-2" tallies would make it obvious who wins the "1" step, so voters would not have to be kept in suspense as the second step proceeded.
 
== For US presidential elections ==
 
In order toTo be usable for US presidential elections, a voting method should be able to work as aan interstate compact alongside other methods. Such an interstate compact would have at most the following steps:
 
# Voters in each state vote using the state's particular voting method.
Line 163 ⟶ 173:
# Possibly looking at the raw totals of other states, each state publishes its final totals.
# Final totals for each state are added and the national winner is found
# IfSignatory states, if they constitute a majority of the electoral college, signatory states are bound by compact to give all their electors to the national winner.
 
In order forFor a voting method to work with this, it must have a feasible way to work with steps 2, 3, and 4.
 
'''Step 2''': "raw totals in some format": many voting methods exist, and many of them require different information from the ballots for summability. One reasonable lowest common denominator would be that all states must publish the rating or ranking levels available, and the raw tallies — the number of times each candidate is rated or ranked at each level. This is far less information than would be required to find a winner under IRV or Condorcet, but it is enough for 3-2-1, when combined with the following steps. It is also information that naturally would always be available from states using simpler methods such as plurality or approval.
 
'''Step 4''': In order to add to provide national totals, each state's final totals should be in the form of a point method - that is, approval, score, or bordaBorda ballots, normalized so that each vote is in the range 0-1. This is not an endorsement of approval, score, or bordaBorda as voting methods; it's simply because these point methods are the only methods natively compatible with ballots from states still using plurality.
 
'''Step 3''': So a state using 3-2-1 must be able to look at the raw tallies from other states, and provide final local tallies, such that the following properties are satisfied:
 
* Each individual local ballot contributes between 0 and 1 points to each candidate's final local tally.
Line 182 ⟶ 192:
This procedure works fine in combination with other states using approval voting, plurality voting, or various other methods. It makes it easier for the voters in 3-2-1 states to cast a strategically-optimal vote, but does not give any greater voting power to a 3-2-1 voter over a strategically-optimal plurality or approval voter. In other words, it is still a matter of "one person one vote"; states would have an incentive to adopt 3-2-1 voting, but voters would not be artificially disenfranchised for not passing it, any more than they are already disenfranchised by inferior voting methods like plurality.
 
[[Category:Single-winner voting systemsmethods]]
[[Category:Runoff-based voting methods]]
[[Category:Cardinal voting methods]]
{{fromelectorama}}