Arrow's impossibility theorem

From electowiki
Revision as of 17:01, 9 January 2020 by Dr. Edmonds (talk | contribs) (Point out that Arrows Theorem only applies to Ordinal systems. Many people think that it applies to all systems.)
Wikipedia has an article on:

Arrow’s impossibility theorem, or Arrow’s paradox demonstrates the impossibility of designing a set of rules based on Ordinal Voting for social decision making that would obey every ‘reasonable’ criterion required by society.

The theorem is named after economist Kenneth Arrow, who proved the theorem in his Ph.D. thesis and popularized it in his 1951 book Social Choice and Individual Values. Arrow was a co-recipient of the 1972 Bank of Sweden Prize in Economic Sciences in Memory of Alfred Nobel (popularly known as the “Nobel Prize in Economics”).

The theorem’s content, somewhat simplified, is as follows. A society needs to agree on a preference order among several different options. Each individual in the society has a particular personal preference order. The problem is to find a general mechanism, called a social choice function, which transforms the set of preference orders, one for each individual, into a global societal preference order. This social choice function should have several desirable (“fair”) properties:

  • unrestricted domain or the universality criterion: the social choice function should create a deterministic, complete societal preference order from every possible set of individual preference orders. (The vote must have a result that ranks all possible choices relative to one another, the voting mechanism must be able to process all possible sets of voter preferences, and it should always give the same result for the same votes, without random selection.)
  • non-imposition or citizen sovereignty: every possible societal preference order should be achievable by some set of individual preference orders. (Every result must be achievable somehow.)
  • non-dictatorship: the social choice function should not simply follow the preference order of a single individual while ignoring all others.
  • positive association of social and individual values or monotonicity: if an individual modifies his or her preference order by promoting a certain option, then the societal preference order should respond only by promoting that same option or not changing, never by placing it lower than before. (An individual should not be able to hurt an option by ranking it higher.)
  • independence of irrelevant alternatives: if we restrict attention to a subset of options, and apply the social choice function only to those, then the result should be compatible with the outcome for the whole set of options. (Changes in individuals’ rankings of “irrelevant” alternatives [i.e., ones outside the subset] should have no impact on the societal ranking of the “relevant” subset.)

Arrow’s theorem says that if the decision-making body has at least two members and at least three options to decide among, then it is impossible to design a social choice function that satisfies all these conditions at once.

Another version of Arrow’s theorem can be obtained by replacing the monotonicity criterion with that of:

  • unanimity or Pareto efficiency: if every individual prefers a certain option to another, then so must the resulting societal preference order.

This statement is stronger, because assuming both monotonicity and independence of irrelevant alternatives implies Pareto efficiency.

With a narrower definition of “irrelevant alternatives” which excludes those candidates in the Smith set, some Condorcet methods meet all the criteria.

Statement

No Ordinal Voting system can be designed that always satisfies these three "fairness" criteria:

  1. Pareto Criterion
  2. Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives
  3. There is neither "dictator" nor "prophet": no single voter possesses the power or the knowledge to always determine the group's preference.

Systems which violate only one of Arrow's criteria

MCA-P, as a rated rather than ranked system, violates only unrestricted domain. A system which arbitrarily chose two candidates to go into a runoff would violate only sovereignty. Random ballot violates only non-dictatorship. None of the methods described on this wiki violate only monotonicity. The Schulze method violates only independence of irrelevant alternatives, although it actually satisfies the similar independence of Smith-dominated alternatives criterion.

Systems Which Evade Arrow's Criteria

It is important to note that Arrow's theorem only applies to Ordinal Voting and not Cardinal voting. This means there are several Cardinal systems which pass all three fairness criteria. The typical example is Score voting but there are also several multi-winner systems which pass all three. There are of course Cardinal systems which do not pass all criteria but this is not due to Arrow's theorem. For example Ebert's Method fails Monotonicity.


See also

External links

This page uses Creative Commons Licensed content from Wikipedia (view authors).