Condorcet winner criterion: Difference between revisions

FIxed compromise candidate HTML mess, and added the picture that was linked so it's now inline. Rewrote some parts to emphasize the link between CW and compromise strategy.
(Distinguishing the Condorcet winner criterion from the Condorcet loser criterion. Also, the abbreviation "PC" stands for "personal computer", and anyone who uses that abbreviation for anything else is being a jerk. :-P)
(FIxed compromise candidate HTML mess, and added the picture that was linked so it's now inline. Rewrote some parts to emphasize the link between CW and compromise strategy.)
Line 59:
===Compromise candidate===
 
On a one-dimensional [[political spectrum]], the beats-all winner will be at the position of the median voter. ExampleSee (alsothe seefollowing httpsexample://i.stack.imgur.com/z4bjy.png):<graph>{
 
"version": 2,
[[File:Left,_Center,_Right.png]]
"width": 400,
 
"height": 200,
Supposing this is the voter distribution, with three candidates '''L'''eft, '''C'''enter, and '''R'''ight, with voters concentrated in each area of the distribution as given, with the yellow voters preferring Left, the green preferring Center, and the blue preferring Right. Then the Condorcet winner is Center, because a majority - the Center voters plus the Left voters - prefers Center to Right, and another majority refers Center to Left.
"data": [
 
{
[[Instant-runoff voting]], which does not pass the Condorcet criterion, fails to detect Center's support and thus Center is eliminated early. However, if the majority preferring Center to the IRV winner knew this in advance, they could have used [[compromising]] strategy to force Center to be elected anyway. See below.
"name": "table",
 
"values": [
Note that the "Center" candidate is only the center of the voters' distribution. If this were a conservative party primary, the center of the distribution would likely be a conservative candidate, not a centrist.
{
"x": 0,
"y": 46
},
{
"x": 1,
"y": 10
},
{
"x": 2,
"y": 44
}
]
}
],
"scales": [
{
"name": "x",
"type": "linear",
"range": "width",
"zero": false,
"domain": {
"data": "table",
"field": "x"
}
},
{
"name": "y",
"type": "linear",
"range": "height",
"nice": true,
"domain": {
"data": "table",
"field": "y"
}
}
],
"axes": [
{
"type": "x",
"scale": "x"
},
{
"type": "y",
"scale": "y"
}
],
"marks": [
{
"type": "area",
"from": {
"data": "table"
},
"properties": {
"enter": {
"x": {
"scale": "x",
"field": "x"
},
"y": {
"scale": "y",
"field": "y"
},
"y2": {
"scale": "y",
"value": 0
},
"fill": {
"value": "steelblue"
},
"interpolate": {
"value": "monotone"
}
}
}
}
]
}</graph>Supposing this is the voter distribution, with 3 candidates Leftist, Centrist, Rightist who are each points on the left, center, and right of the distribution respectively, with all voters distributed from left to right, and voters on, for example, the left preferring Leftist>Centrist>Rightist, and the same holding vice versa. The Condorcet winner is the Centrist, because a majority prefer them over the "other side", for whichever side you look at.
 
===Equilibrium point for various voting methods===
The Condorcet winner/[[Smith set]] is a common [[equilibrium]] point in many voting methods. This is because a majority/plurality of voters have no incentive to deviate towards another candidate. ExampleThe forCondorcet criterion can thus be considered a type of [[ApprovalDeclared strategy voting|automatic strategy]]:, which reduces the need for [[compromising]] strategy by electing candidates who could have won with majority-strength compromising.
 
An example for [[Approval voting]]:
 
35: A>B|>C
Line 221 ⟶ 146:
==Strategic implications==
 
Every Condorcet method is susceptible to burial in at least some elections, and Condorcet is also incompatible with [[later-no-harm]] and [[later-no-help]]. However, if a method haspasses the property[[informed thatmajority coalition criterion]] so a coordinated majority can always force its outcome, then prefixing a Condorcet step to that method can never increase the proportion of elections where strategy pays off.<ref name="Green-Armytage Tideman Cosman pp. 183–212">{{cite journal | last=Green-Armytage | first=James | last2=Tideman | first2=T. Nicolaus | last3=Cosman | first3=Rafael | title=Statistical evaluation of voting rules | journal=Social Choice and Welfare | publisher=Springer Science and Business Media LLC | volume=46 | issue=1 | date=2015-08-11 | issn=0176-1714 | doi=10.1007/s00355-015-0909-0 | pages=183–212|url=http://jamesgreenarmytage.com/strategy-utility.pdf}}</ref><ref name="Durand Mathieu Noirie 2014">{{cite web | last=Durand | first=François | last2=Mathieu | first2=Fabien | last3=Noirie | first3=Ludovic | title=Making most voting systems meet the Condorcet criterion reduces their manipulability | website=Inria | date=2014-06-17 | url=https://hal.inria.fr/hal-01009134 | access-date=2022-01-12}}</ref>
 
==Criticism==
1,204

edits