Participation criterion: Difference between revisions

Add limit on how many voters can be present for there to exist a voting rule passing both Condorcet and participation.
(Linking to ranked voting)
(Add limit on how many voters can be present for there to exist a voting rule passing both Condorcet and participation.)
 
(3 intermediate revisions by the same user not shown)
Line 5:
While the criterion ensures that a voter can't benefit from staying home rather than voting honestly, a voter may do even better by engaging in [[tactical voting]]; participation does not imply that the method is strategy-proof.
 
== Statement of CriterionDefinition ==
 
For deterministic single-winner methods, the criterion is defined as follows:
Line 11:
{{definition|Adding one or more ballots that vote X over Y should never change the winner from X to Y.}}
 
For multi-winner methods and methods that involve an element of chance, the definition is:<ref name="Woodall-Monotonicity">D{{cite Rjournal| title = Monotonicity and single-seat election rules| last = Woodall,| [first = Douglas R.| journal = Voting matters| volume = 6| pages = 9–14| year = 1996|url=http://www.votingmatters.org.uk/ISSUE6/P4.HTM "Monotonicity and Single-Seat Election Rules"], ''[[Voting matters]]'', Issue 6, 1996}}</ref>
 
{{definition|The addition of a further ballot should not, for any positive whole number k, reduce the probability that at least one candidate is elected out of the first k candidates listed on that ballot.}}
 
== Variants ==
 
=== Weak Participation criterion===
 
By voting, you cannot cause X to be elected instead of Y (with all other winners staying the same) if you scored Y higher than X. One consequence of this criteria, is that by voting, you can never get a result that is less desirable according to your ballot then a result that is more desirable according to your ballot. The difference between this criterion and the strong Strong Participation criterion is that because unless there was an infinite range for you to score candidates on (you are scoring candidates on infinite sliding bars), due to the approximations you make when expressing your utilities on a finite number of scores, your ballot can disagree with you about whether outcome X is better than outcome Y.
 
(Described here: [https://rangevoting.org/QualityMulti.html#faildesid "Optimal proportional representation" multiwinner voting systems I: methods, algorithms, advantages, and inherent flaws])
 
=== Semi-honest participation criterion ===
This is a weaker form of the [[participation criterion]]. It states that for any set of ballots, an extra voter with a given preference set must be able to cast a ballot which is semi-honest and meaningfully expressive, without making the result worse. Meaningfully expressive means that if the voter prefers some set of candidates to the winner, the non-harmful ballot must be able to express that preference.
 
== Complying Methodsmethods ==
 
This criterion is important in the context of the [[Balinski–Young theorem]]. Failing the participation criterion is an an example of failing [[Populationpopulation monotonicity]].
== Complying Methods ==
 
This criterion is important in the context of the [[Balinski–Young theorem]]. Failing the participation criterion is an an example of failing [[Population monotonicity]].
 
Every [[weighted positional method]] that gives higher ranked candidates higher scores passes the participation criterion. In particular, [[Plurality voting]] and the [[Borda count]] both pass. Furthermore, [[Approval voting]], [[Cardinal Ratings]], and Woodall's [[Descending Acquiescing Coalitions|DAC]] and [[Descending Solid Coalitions|DSC]] methods all pass the participation criterion. All [[Condorcet method]]s,<ref name=":0">{{Cite journal|last=Moulin|first=Hervé|date=1988-06-01|title=Condorcet's principle implies the no show paradox|journal=Journal of Economic Theory|volume=45|issue=1|pages=53–64|doi=10.1016/0022-0531(88)90253-0}}</ref><ref>{{cite web|url=http://rangevoting.org/CondPF.html|title=Participation failure" is forced in Condorcet methods with at least 4 candidates|accessdate=2014-12-24}}</ref> [[Bucklin voting]],<ref>{{cite web|url=http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/1998-June/001727.html|title=Regretted Turnout. Insincere = ranking.|author=Markus Schulze|accessdate=2011-05-14|date=1998-06-12}}</ref> and [[instant-runoff voting|IRV]]<ref name="WDSParticipationReversalSymmetry">{{cite web|author=Warren D. Smith|url=http://rangevoting.org/TBlecture.html#partic|title=Lecture "Mathematics and Democracy"|accessdate=2011-05-12}}</ref> fail.
 
It's possible to pass both Condorcet and Participation for three candidates and any number of voters, or for four candidates up to 11 voters inclusive.<ref name="Brandt Geist Peters 2016">{{cite arXiv | last=Brandt | first=Felix | last2=Geist | first2=Christian | last3=Peters | first3=Dominik | title=Optimal Bounds for the No-Show Paradox via SAT Solving | date=2016-02-25 | eprint=1602.08063 | class=cs.GT }}</ref> This result also holds for certain probabilistic extensions of the Condorcet criterion.
 
All Monroe type multi-member systems fail participation.
 
''Some parts of this article are derived with permission from text at http://electionmethods.org''
 
== Notes ==
Line 54 ⟶ 47:
*[[Weak Defensive Strategy criterion]]
*[[Favorite Betrayal criterion]]
*
*[[Summability criterion]]
 
== References ==
<references/>
 
''Some parts of this article are derived with permission from text at http://electionmethods.org''
 
== External links ==
1,196

edits