Cardinal voting systems: Difference between revisions

Content added Content deleted
(→‎Single Member Methods: removing double redirect)
(→‎Applicability of Arrow's theorem: Clear up some misconceptions)
Line 106: Line 106:
Normalization can also more broadly refer to when a voter's rated ballot is adjusted to fit between any two scores i.e. if the highest score a voter gave anyone was a 3 out of 5, then in some situations, it is desirable to ensure that after normalization, the voter's highest score given to any candidate will still be a 3 out of 5. This can be the case when a voter does not want to use all of their voting power.
Normalization can also more broadly refer to when a voter's rated ballot is adjusted to fit between any two scores i.e. if the highest score a voter gave anyone was a 3 out of 5, then in some situations, it is desirable to ensure that after normalization, the voter's highest score given to any candidate will still be a 3 out of 5. This can be the case when a voter does not want to use all of their voting power.


===Impossibility Theorems===
===Applicability of Arrow's theorem===
:''{{Main|Arrow's impossibility theorem}}''
:''{{Main|Arrow's impossibility theorem}}''
[[Arrow's impossibility theorem]] demonstrates the impossibility of designing a set of rules for social decision making that would obey every ‘reasonable’ criterion required by society. Some activists believe that Arrow's theorem only applies to [[ordinal voting]] and not cardinal voting. They point out that that it is technically possible for several cardinal systems to pass all three fairness criteria. The typical example is [[score voting]] but there are also several [[Multi-Member System |multi-winner systems]] which proport to pass all three of Arrow's original criteria. Additionally, there are cardinal systems which do not pass all criteria but this is not due to Arrow's theorem; for example [[Ebert's Method]] fails [[Monotonicity]].
[[Arrow's impossibility theorem]] demonstrates the impossibility of designing an [[Ordinal voting]] system which passes a set of desirable criteria. Since Arrow's theorem only applies to [[ordinal voting]] and not cardinal voting systems, several cardinal systems to pass all these criteria. The typical example is [[score voting]] but there are also several [[Multi-Member System |multi-winner systems]] which pass all three of Arrow's original criteria. Additionally, there are cardinal systems which do not pass all criteria but this is not due to Arrow's theorem; for example [[Ebert's Method]] fails [[Monotonicity]]. Subsequent social choice theorists have expanded on Arrow's central insight, and applied his ideas to specific cardinal systems.


However, subsequent social choice theorists have expanded on Arrow's central insight, and applied his ideas more broadly. For example, the [[Gibbard-Satterthwaite theorem]] (published in 1973) holds that any deterministic process of collective decision making with multiple options will have some level of [[strategic voting]]. As a result of this much of the work of social choice theorists is to find out what types of [[strategic voting]] a system is susceptible to and the level of susceptibility for each. For example [[Single Member system | Single Member systems]] are not susceptible to [[Free riding]].
Furthermore, there are other [[Voting paradox| Impossibility Theorems]] which are different than Arrow's and apply to cardinal systems. The most relevant are the [[Gibbard-Satterthwaite theorem]] and the [[Balinski–Young theorem]]. The [[Gibbard-Satterthwaite theorem]] (published in 1973) holds that any deterministic process of collective decision making with multiple options will have some level of [[strategic voting]]. As a result of this much of the work of social choice theorists is to find out what types of [[strategic voting]] a system is susceptible to and the level of susceptibility for each. For example [[Single Member system | Single Member systems]] are not susceptible to [[Free riding]]. The [[Balinski–Young theorem]] holds that a system cannot satisfy a [[Quota rule | Quota Rule]] while having both [[House monotonicity criterion | House monotonicity]] and [[Population monotonicity]]. This is important because quota rules are used in most definitions of [[Proportional representation]] and [[Population monotonicity]] is intimatly tied to the [[Participation criterion]].